1
|
Kong Q, Cheung H. Investigating 18-month-olds’ association-based inferences in an interactive unexpected-identity paradigm. COGNITIVE DEVELOPMENT 2021. [DOI: 10.1016/j.cogdev.2021.101051] [Citation(s) in RCA: 0] [Impact Index Per Article: 0] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 11/16/2022]
|
2
|
Baratgin J, Dubois-Sage M, Jacquet B, Stilgenbauer JL, Jamet F. Pragmatics in the False-Belief Task: Let the Robot Ask the Question! Front Psychol 2020; 11:593807. [PMID: 33329255 PMCID: PMC7719623 DOI: 10.3389/fpsyg.2020.593807] [Citation(s) in RCA: 2] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.4] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [Track Full Text] [Download PDF] [Figures] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 08/11/2020] [Accepted: 10/28/2020] [Indexed: 11/13/2022] Open
Abstract
The poor performances of typically developing children younger than 4 in the first-order false-belief task "Maxi and the chocolate" is analyzed from the perspective of conversational pragmatics. An ambiguous question asked by an adult experimenter (perceived as a teacher) can receive different interpretations based on a search for relevance, by which children according to their age attribute different intentions to the questioner, within the limits of their own meta-cognitive knowledge. The adult experimenter tells the child the following story of object-transfer: "Maxi puts his chocolate into the green cupboard before going out to play. In his absence, his mother moves the chocolate from the green cupboard to the blue one." The child must then predict where Maxi will pick up the chocolate when he returns. To the child, the question from an adult (a knowledgeable person) may seem surprising and can be understood as a question of his own knowledge of the world, rather than on Maxi's mental representations. In our study, without any modification of the initial task, we disambiguate the context of the question by (1) replacing the adult experimenter with a humanoid robot presented as "ignorant" and "slow" but trying to learn and (2) placing the child in the role of a "mentor" (the knowledgeable person). Sixty-two typical children of 3 years-old completed the first-order false belief task "Maxi and the chocolate," either with a human or with a robot. Results revealed a significantly higher success rate in the robot condition than in the human condition. Thus, young children seem to fail because of the pragmatic difficulty of the first-order task, which causes a difference of interpretation between the young child and the experimenter.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Jean Baratgin
- Laboratoire Cognition Humaine et Artificielle, Université Paris 8, Paris, France
- Probability, Assessment, Reasoning and Inferences Studies (P-A-R-I-S) Association, Paris, France
| | - Marion Dubois-Sage
- Laboratoire Cognition Humaine et Artificielle, Université Paris 8, Paris, France
- Probability, Assessment, Reasoning and Inferences Studies (P-A-R-I-S) Association, Paris, France
| | - Baptiste Jacquet
- Laboratoire Cognition Humaine et Artificielle, Université Paris 8, Paris, France
- Probability, Assessment, Reasoning and Inferences Studies (P-A-R-I-S) Association, Paris, France
| | - Jean-Louis Stilgenbauer
- Laboratoire Cognition Humaine et Artificielle, Université Paris 8, Paris, France
- Probability, Assessment, Reasoning and Inferences Studies (P-A-R-I-S) Association, Paris, France
- Facultés Libres de Philosophie et de Psychologie (IPC), Paris, France
| | - Frank Jamet
- Laboratoire Cognition Humaine et Artificielle, Université Paris 8, Paris, France
- Probability, Assessment, Reasoning and Inferences Studies (P-A-R-I-S) Association, Paris, France
- CY Cergy-Paris Université, ESPE de Versailles, Paris, France
| |
Collapse
|
3
|
Buttelmann F, Kovács ÁM. 14-Month-olds anticipate others' actions based on their belief about an object's identity. INFANCY 2020; 24:738-751. [PMID: 32677281 DOI: 10.1111/infa.12303] [Citation(s) in RCA: 6] [Impact Index Per Article: 1.2] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 07/14/2018] [Revised: 02/11/2019] [Accepted: 05/18/2019] [Indexed: 11/27/2022]
Abstract
Past research has accumulated evidence regarding infants' false-belief understanding, measuring their gaze patterns or active helping behaviors. However, the underlying mechanisms are still debated, specifically, whether young infants can compute that others represent the world under a certain aspect. Such performance requires holding in mind two representations about the same object simultaneously and attributing only one to another person. While 14-month-olds can encode an object under different aspects when forming first-person representations, it is unclear whether infants at this very age could also predict others' behavior based on their beliefs about an object's identity. Here, we investigate this question in a novel eye-tracking-based unexpected-identity task. We measured 14-month-olds' anticipatory looks combined with their looking time, using a violation-of-expectation paradigm. Results show that 14-month-olds look longer to an actor's reach that is incongruent with her false belief about the identity of an object compared to a congruent reach. Furthermore, infants correctly anticipated the actor's reach based on her false belief. Thus, as soon as infants represent dual identities they can integrate them in belief attributions and use them for consequent behavioral predictions. Such data provide evidence for the flexibility of false-belief attributions and support proposals arguing for infants' rich theory-of-mind abilities.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Frances Buttelmann
- Department of Developmental Psychology, Friedrich Schiller University, Jena, Germany
| | | |
Collapse
|
4
|
|
5
|
Schuwerk T, Priewasser B, Sodian B, Perner J. The robustness and generalizability of findings on spontaneous false belief sensitivity: a replication attempt. ROYAL SOCIETY OPEN SCIENCE 2018; 5:172273. [PMID: 29892412 PMCID: PMC5990829 DOI: 10.1098/rsos.172273] [Citation(s) in RCA: 36] [Impact Index Per Article: 5.1] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [Grants] [Track Full Text] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 12/19/2017] [Accepted: 03/23/2018] [Indexed: 06/01/2023]
Abstract
Influential studies showed that 25-month-olds and neurotypical adults take an agent's false belief into account in their anticipatory looking patterns (Southgate et al. 2007 Psychol. Sci.18, 587-592 (doi:10.1111/j.1467-9280.2007.01944.x); Senju et al. 2009 Science325, 883-885 (doi:10.1126/science.1176170)). These findings constitute central pillars of current accounts distinguishing between implicit and explicit Theory of Mind. In our first experiment, which initially included a replication as well as two manipulations, we failed to replicate the original finding in 2- to 3-year-olds (N = 48). Therefore, we ran a second experiment with the sole purpose of seeing whether the effect can be found in an independent, tightly controlled, sufficiently powered and preregistered replication study. This replication attempt failed again in a sample of 25-month-olds (N = 78), but was successful in a sample of adults (N = 115). In all samples, a surprisingly high number of participants did not correctly anticipate the agent's action during the familiarization phase. This led to massive exclusion rates when adhering to the criteria of the original studies and strongly limits the interpretability of findings from the test phase. We discuss both the reliability of our replication attempts as well as the replicability of non-verbal anticipatory looking paradigms of implicit false belief sensitivity, in general.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Tobias Schuwerk
- Department of Psychology, Ludwig-Maximilians-University, Munich, Germany
| | - Beate Priewasser
- Department of Psychology, University of Salzburg, Salzburg, Austria
- Centre for Cognitive Neuroscience, University of Salzburg, Salzburg, Austria
| | - Beate Sodian
- Department of Psychology, Ludwig-Maximilians-University, Munich, Germany
| | - Josef Perner
- Department of Psychology, University of Salzburg, Salzburg, Austria
- Centre for Cognitive Neuroscience, University of Salzburg, Salzburg, Austria
| |
Collapse
|
6
|
The biocultural emergence of mindreading: integrating cognitive archaeology and human development. JOURNAL OF CULTURAL COGNITIVE SCIENCE 2017. [DOI: 10.1007/s41809-017-0008-0] [Citation(s) in RCA: 10] [Impact Index Per Article: 1.3] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 11/25/2022]
|
7
|
Meert G, Wang J, Samson D. Efficient belief tracking in adults: The role of task instruction, low-level associative processes and dispositional social functioning. Cognition 2017; 168:91-98. [DOI: 10.1016/j.cognition.2017.06.012] [Citation(s) in RCA: 4] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.5] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 03/09/2016] [Revised: 06/09/2017] [Accepted: 06/12/2017] [Indexed: 12/19/2022]
|
8
|
Attentional processes, not implicit mentalizing, mediate performance in a perspective-taking task: Evidence from stimulation of the temporoparietal junction. Neuroimage 2017; 155:305-311. [DOI: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2017.04.055] [Citation(s) in RCA: 26] [Impact Index Per Article: 3.3] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 01/06/2017] [Revised: 04/22/2017] [Accepted: 04/24/2017] [Indexed: 11/17/2022] Open
|
9
|
Scott RM, Baillargeon R. Early False-Belief Understanding. Trends Cogn Sci 2017; 21:237-249. [DOI: 10.1016/j.tics.2017.01.012] [Citation(s) in RCA: 90] [Impact Index Per Article: 11.3] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 12/14/2016] [Revised: 01/24/2017] [Accepted: 01/26/2017] [Indexed: 10/20/2022]
|
10
|
Paulus M, Schuwerk T, Sodian B, Ganglmayer K. Children’s and adults’ use of verbal information to visually anticipate others’ actions: A study on explicit and implicit social-cognitive processing. Cognition 2017; 160:145-152. [DOI: 10.1016/j.cognition.2016.12.013] [Citation(s) in RCA: 7] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.9] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 08/07/2016] [Revised: 12/22/2016] [Accepted: 12/28/2016] [Indexed: 11/24/2022]
|
11
|
Perspectives on Perspective Taking: How Children Think About the Minds of Others. ADVANCES IN CHILD DEVELOPMENT AND BEHAVIOR 2017; 52:185-226. [PMID: 28215285 DOI: 10.1016/bs.acdb.2016.10.005] [Citation(s) in RCA: 17] [Impact Index Per Article: 2.1] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [Track Full Text] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 11/22/2022]
Abstract
Perspective taking, or "theory of mind," involves reasoning about the mental states of others (e.g., their intentions, desires, knowledge, beliefs) and is called upon in virtually every aspect of human interaction. Our goals in writing this chapter were to provide an overview of (a) the research questions developmental psychologists ask to shed light on how children think about the inner workings of the mind, and (b) why such research is invaluable in understanding human nature and our ability to interact with, and learn from, one another. We begin with a brief review of early research in this field that culminated in the so-called litmus test for a theory of mind (i.e., false-belief tasks). Next, we describe research with infants and young children that created a puzzle for many researchers, and briefly mention an intriguing approach researchers have used to attempt to "solve" this puzzle. We then turn to research examining children's understanding of a much broader range of mental states (beyond false beliefs). We briefly discuss the value of studying individual differences by highlighting their important implications for social well-being and ways to improve perspective taking. Next, we review work illustrating the value of capitalizing on children's proclivity for selective social learning to reveal their understanding of others' mental states. We close by highlighting one line of research that we believe will be an especially fruitful avenue for future research and serves to emphasize the complex interplay between our perspective-taking abilities and other cognitive processes.
Collapse
|
12
|
Todd AR, Simpson AJ. Anxiety impairs spontaneous perspective calculation: Evidence from a level-1 visual perspective-taking task. Cognition 2016; 156:88-94. [DOI: 10.1016/j.cognition.2016.08.004] [Citation(s) in RCA: 16] [Impact Index Per Article: 1.8] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 06/04/2016] [Revised: 07/25/2016] [Accepted: 08/04/2016] [Indexed: 10/21/2022]
|
13
|
Schuwerk T, Paulus M. Preschoolers, adolescents, and adults visually anticipate an agent's efficient action; but only after having observed it frequently. Q J Exp Psychol (Hove) 2016; 69:800-16. [DOI: 10.1080/17470218.2015.1061028] [Citation(s) in RCA: 9] [Impact Index Per Article: 1.0] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 10/23/2022]
Abstract
The present study examined the contribution of efficiency reasoning and statistical learning on visual action anticipation in preschool children, adolescents, and adults. To this end, Experiment 1 assessed proactive eye movements of 5-year-old children, 15-year-old adolescents, and adults, who observed an agent stating the intent to reach a goal as quickly as possible. Subsequently the agent could four times either take a short, hence efficient, or long, hence inefficient, path to get to the goal. The results showed that in the first trial participants in none of the age groups predicted above chance level that the agent would produce the efficient action. Instead, we observed an age-dependent increase in action predictions in the subsequent repeated presentation of the same action. Experiment 2 ruled out that participants’ nonconsideration of the efficient path was due to a lack of understanding of the agent's action goal. Moreover, it demonstrated that 5-year-old children do predict that the agent will act efficiently when verbally reasoning about his future action. Overall, the study supports the view that rapid learning from frequency information guides visual action anticipations.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Tobias Schuwerk
- Department of Psychology, Ludwig-Maximilians Universität München, Munich, Germany
- Department of Psychiatry and Psychotherapy, University of Regensburg, Regensburg, Germany
| | - Markus Paulus
- Department of Psychology, Ludwig-Maximilians Universität München, Munich, Germany
| |
Collapse
|
14
|
Rubio-Fernández P. Can We Forget What We Know in a False-Belief Task? An Investigation of the True-Belief Default. Cogn Sci 2015; 41:218-241. [PMID: 26706462 DOI: 10.1111/cogs.12331] [Citation(s) in RCA: 4] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.4] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 07/14/2014] [Revised: 09/01/2015] [Accepted: 09/10/2015] [Indexed: 11/27/2022]
Abstract
It has been generally assumed in the Theory of Mind literature of the past 30 years that young children fail standard false-belief tasks because they attribute their own knowledge to the protagonist (what Leslie and colleagues called a "true-belief default"). Contrary to the traditional view, we have recently proposed that the children's bias is task induced. This alternative view was supported by studies showing that 3 year olds are able to pass a false-belief task that allows them to focus on the protagonist, without drawing their attention to the target object in the test phase. For a more accurate comparison of these two accounts, the present study tested the true-belief default with adults. Four experiments measuring eye movements and response inhibition revealed that (a) adults do not have an automatic tendency to respond to the false-belief question according to their own knowledge and (b) the true-belief response need not be inhibited in order to correctly predict the protagonist's actions. The positive results observed in the control conditions confirm the accuracy of the various measures used. I conclude that the results of this study undermine the true-belief default view and those models that posit mechanisms of response inhibition in false-belief reasoning. Alternatively, the present study with adults and recent studies with children suggest that participants' focus of attention in false-belief tasks may be key to their performance.
Collapse
|
15
|
|
16
|
What you get is what you believe: Eighteen-month-olds demonstrate belief understanding in an unexpected-identity task. J Exp Child Psychol 2015; 131:94-103. [DOI: 10.1016/j.jecp.2014.11.009] [Citation(s) in RCA: 48] [Impact Index Per Article: 4.8] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 05/27/2014] [Revised: 11/26/2014] [Accepted: 11/26/2014] [Indexed: 11/17/2022]
|
17
|
Heyes C. False belief in infancy: a fresh look. Dev Sci 2014; 17:647-59. [PMID: 24666559 DOI: 10.1111/desc.12148] [Citation(s) in RCA: 158] [Impact Index Per Article: 14.4] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 10/31/2012] [Accepted: 09/29/2013] [Indexed: 11/30/2022]
Abstract
Can infants appreciate that others have false beliefs? Do they have a theory of mind? In this article I provide a detailed review of more than 20 experiments that have addressed these questions, and offered an affirmative answer, using nonverbal 'violation of expectation' and 'anticipatory looking' procedures. Although many of these experiments are both elegant and ingenious, I argue that their results can be explained by the operation of domain-general processes and in terms of 'low-level novelty'. This hypothesis suggests that the infants' looking behaviour is a function of the degree to which the observed (perceptual novelty) and remembered or expected (imaginal novelty) low-level properties of the test stimuli - their colours, shapes and movements - are novel with respect to events encoded by the infants earlier in the experiment. If the low-level novelty hypothesis is correct, research on false belief in infancy currently falls short of demonstrating that infants have even an implicit theory of mind. However, I suggest that the use of two experimental strategies - inanimate control procedures, and self-informed belief induction - could be used in combination with existing methods to bring us much closer to understanding the evolutionary and developmental origins of theory of mind.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Cecilia Heyes
- All Souls College & Department of Experimental Psychology, University of Oxford, UK
| |
Collapse
|
18
|
Thompson JR. Signature limits in mindreading systems. Cogn Sci 2014; 38:1432-55. [PMID: 24646207 DOI: 10.1111/cogs.12117] [Citation(s) in RCA: 9] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.8] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 09/20/2012] [Revised: 07/11/2013] [Accepted: 07/22/2013] [Indexed: 11/30/2022]
Abstract
Recent evidence that young children seem to both understand false belief in one sense, but not in another, has led to two-systems theorizing about mindreading. By analyzing the most detailed two-systems approach in studying social cognition-the theory of mindreading defended by Ian Apperly and Stephen Butterfill-I argue that that even when dutifully constructed, two-systems approaches in social cognition struggle to adequately define the mindreading systems in terms of signature processing limits, an issue that becomes most apparent when investigating mindreading in infancy. I end the article by developing several challenges that face any two-systems account of mindreading.
Collapse
|
19
|
|
20
|
Rubio-Fernández P. Perspective tracking in progress: Do not disturb. Cognition 2013; 129:264-72. [DOI: 10.1016/j.cognition.2013.07.005] [Citation(s) in RCA: 24] [Impact Index Per Article: 2.0] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 12/18/2012] [Revised: 07/06/2013] [Accepted: 07/08/2013] [Indexed: 10/26/2022]
|
21
|
What do infants understand of others’ action? A theoretical account of early social cognition. PSYCHOLOGICAL RESEARCH 2013; 78:609-22. [DOI: 10.1007/s00426-013-0519-3] [Citation(s) in RCA: 32] [Impact Index Per Article: 2.7] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 05/30/2013] [Accepted: 09/26/2013] [Indexed: 10/26/2022]
|
22
|
Abstract
The experimental record of the last three decades shows that children under 4 years old fail all sorts of variations on the standard false-belief task, whereas more recent studies have revealed that infants are able to pass nonverbal versions of the task. We argue that these paradoxical results are an artifact of the type of false-belief tasks that have been used to test infants and children: Nonverbal designs allow infants to keep track of a protagonist's perspective over a course of events, whereas verbal designs tend to disrupt the perspective-tracking process in various ways, which makes it too hard for younger children to demonstrate their capacity for perspective tracking. We report three experiments that confirm this hypothesis by showing that 3-year-olds can pass a suitably streamlined version of the verbal false-belief task. We conclude that young children can pass the verbal false-belief task provided that they are allowed to keep track of the protagonist's perspective without too much disruption.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Paula Rubio-Fernández
- Division of Psychology and Language Sciences, University College London, 2 Wakefield St., London, United Kingdom.
| | | |
Collapse
|
23
|
de Bruin L, van Elk M, Newen A. Reconceptualizing second-person interaction. Front Hum Neurosci 2012; 6:151. [PMID: 22679421 PMCID: PMC3368580 DOI: 10.3389/fnhum.2012.00151] [Citation(s) in RCA: 14] [Impact Index Per Article: 1.1] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [Track Full Text] [Download PDF] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 02/29/2012] [Accepted: 05/14/2012] [Indexed: 11/13/2022] Open
Abstract
Over the last couple of decades, most neuroscientific research on social cognition has been dominated by a third-person paradigm in which participating subjects are not actively engaging with other agents but merely observe them. Recently this paradigm has been challenged by researchers who promote a second-person approach to social cognition, and emphasize the importance of dynamic, real-time interactions with others. The present article's contribution to this debate is twofold. First, we critically analyze the second-person challenge to social neuroscience, and assess the various ways in which the distinction between second- versus third-person modes of social cognition has been articulated. Second, we put forward an alternative conceptualization of this distinction-one that gives pride of place to the notion of reciprocity. We discuss the implications of our proposal for neuroscientific studies on social cognition.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Leon de Bruin
- Department of Philosophy II, Ruhr-University Bochum Bochum, Germany
| | | | | |
Collapse
|
24
|
Paulus M. Is It Rational to Assume that Infants Imitate Rationally? A Theoretical Analysis and Critique. Hum Dev 2012. [DOI: 10.1159/000339442] [Citation(s) in RCA: 16] [Impact Index Per Article: 1.2] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 11/19/2022]
|