1
|
Neafsey EJ. Conscious intention and human action: Review of the rise and fall of the readiness potential and Libet's clock. Conscious Cogn 2021; 94:103171. [PMID: 34325185 DOI: 10.1016/j.concog.2021.103171] [Citation(s) in RCA: 8] [Impact Index Per Article: 2.0] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 01/20/2021] [Revised: 06/26/2021] [Accepted: 07/04/2021] [Indexed: 11/15/2022]
Abstract
Is consciousness-the subjective awareness of the sensations, perceptions, beliefs, desires, and intentions of mental life-a genuine cause of human action or a mere impotent epiphenomenon accompanying the brain's physical activity but utterly incapable of making anything actually happen? This article will review the history and current status of experiments and commentary related to Libet's influential paper (Brain 106:623-664, 1983) whose conclusion "that cerebral initiation even of a spontaneous voluntary act …can and usually does begin unconsciously" has had a huge effect on debate about the efficacy of conscious intentions. Early (up to 2008) and more recent (2008 on) experiments replicating and criticizing Libet's conclusions and especially his methods will be discussed, focusing especially on recent observations that the readiness potential (RP) may only be an "artifact of averaging" and that, when intention is measured using "tone probes," the onset of intention is found much earlier and often before the onset of the RP. Based on these findings, Libet's methodology was flawed and his results are no longer valid reasons for rejecting Fodor's "good old commonsense belief/desire psychology" that "my wanting is causally responsible for my reaching.".
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Edward J Neafsey
- Loyola University Chicago Stritch School of Medicine, Department of Molecular Pharmacology and Neuroscience, 2160 S. First Ave., Maywood, IL 60153, United States.
| |
Collapse
|
2
|
Schultze-Kraft M, Parés-Pujolràs E, Matić K, Haggard P, Haynes JD. Preparation and execution of voluntary action both contribute to awareness of intention. Proc Biol Sci 2020; 287:20192928. [PMID: 32208835 DOI: 10.1098/rspb.2019.2928] [Citation(s) in RCA: 6] [Impact Index Per Article: 1.2] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 11/12/2022] Open
Abstract
How and when motor intentions form has long been controversial. In particular, the extent to which motor preparation and action-related processes produce a conscious experience of intention remains unknown. Here, we used a brain-computer interface (BCI) while participants performed a self-paced movement task to trigger cues upon the detection of a readiness potential (a well-characterized brain signal that precedes movement) or in its absence. The BCI-triggered cues instructed participants either to move or not to move. Following this instruction, participants reported whether they felt they were about to move at the time the cue was presented. Participants were more likely to report an intention (i) when the cue was triggered by the presence of a readiness potential than when the same cue was triggered by its absence, and (ii) when they had just made an action than when they had not. We further describe a time-dependent integration of these two factors: the probability of reporting an intention was maximal when cues were triggered in the presence of a readiness potential, and when participants also executed an action shortly afterwards. Our results provide a first systematic investigation of how prospective and retrospective components are integrated in forming a conscious intention to move.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Matthias Schultze-Kraft
- Bernstein Center for Computational Neuroscience, Charité-Universitätsmedizin Berlin, Berlin, Germany.,Berlin Center for Advanced Neuroimaging, Charité-Universitätsmedizin Berlin, Berlin, Germany.,SFB 940 Volition and Cognitive Control, Technische Universität Dresden, Dresden, Germany
| | | | - Karla Matić
- Bernstein Center for Computational Neuroscience, Charité-Universitätsmedizin Berlin, Berlin, Germany.,Laboratory of Experimental Psychology, KU Leuven, Louvain, Belgium
| | - Patrick Haggard
- Institute of Cognitive Neuroscience, University College London, London, UK.,Laboratoire des Neuroscience Cognitives, Département d'Études Cognitives, École Normale Supérieure, PSL University, Paris, France
| | - John-Dylan Haynes
- Bernstein Center for Computational Neuroscience, Charité-Universitätsmedizin Berlin, Berlin, Germany.,Berlin Center for Advanced Neuroimaging, Charité-Universitätsmedizin Berlin, Berlin, Germany.,Clinic of Neurology, Charité-Universitätsmedizin Berlin, Berlin, Germany.,SFB 940 Volition and Cognitive Control, Technische Universität Dresden, Dresden, Germany.,Department of Psychology, Humboldt Universität zu Berlin, Berlin, Germany.,Excellence Cluster Science of Intelligence, Technische Universität Berlin and Humbold Universität zu Berlin, Berlin, Germany
| |
Collapse
|
3
|
Schultze-Kraft M, Birman D, Rusconi M, Allefeld C, Görgen K, Dähne S, Blankertz B, Haynes JD. The point of no return in vetoing self-initiated movements. Proc Natl Acad Sci U S A 2016; 113:1080-5. [PMID: 26668390 PMCID: PMC4743787 DOI: 10.1073/pnas.1513569112] [Citation(s) in RCA: 90] [Impact Index Per Article: 10.0] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [MESH Headings] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 12/11/2022] Open
Abstract
In humans, spontaneous movements are often preceded by early brain signals. One such signal is the readiness potential (RP) that gradually arises within the last second preceding a movement. An important question is whether people are able to cancel movements after the elicitation of such RPs, and if so until which point in time. Here, subjects played a game where they tried to press a button to earn points in a challenge with a brain-computer interface (BCI) that had been trained to detect their RPs in real time and to emit stop signals. Our data suggest that subjects can still veto a movement even after the onset of the RP. Cancellation of movements was possible if stop signals occurred earlier than 200 ms before movement onset, thus constituting a point of no return.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Matthias Schultze-Kraft
- Bernstein Center for Computational Neuroscience, Charité-Universitätsmedizin Berlin, 10117 Berlin, Germany; Neurotechnology Group, Technische Universität Berlin, 10587 Berlin, Germany; Bernstein Focus: Neurotechnology, Technische Universität Berlin, 10587 Berlin, Germany;
| | - Daniel Birman
- Bernstein Center for Computational Neuroscience, Charité-Universitätsmedizin Berlin, 10117 Berlin, Germany; Berlin Center for Advanced Neuroimaging, Charité-Universitätsmedizin Berlin, 10117 Berlin, Germany
| | - Marco Rusconi
- Bernstein Center for Computational Neuroscience, Charité-Universitätsmedizin Berlin, 10117 Berlin, Germany; Berlin Center for Advanced Neuroimaging, Charité-Universitätsmedizin Berlin, 10117 Berlin, Germany
| | - Carsten Allefeld
- Bernstein Center for Computational Neuroscience, Charité-Universitätsmedizin Berlin, 10117 Berlin, Germany; Berlin Center for Advanced Neuroimaging, Charité-Universitätsmedizin Berlin, 10117 Berlin, Germany
| | - Kai Görgen
- Bernstein Center for Computational Neuroscience, Charité-Universitätsmedizin Berlin, 10117 Berlin, Germany; Berlin Center for Advanced Neuroimaging, Charité-Universitätsmedizin Berlin, 10117 Berlin, Germany
| | - Sven Dähne
- Machine Leaning Group, Technische Universität Berlin, 10587 Berlin, Germany
| | - Benjamin Blankertz
- Bernstein Center for Computational Neuroscience, Charité-Universitätsmedizin Berlin, 10117 Berlin, Germany; Neurotechnology Group, Technische Universität Berlin, 10587 Berlin, Germany; Bernstein Focus: Neurotechnology, Technische Universität Berlin, 10587 Berlin, Germany
| | - John-Dylan Haynes
- Bernstein Center for Computational Neuroscience, Charité-Universitätsmedizin Berlin, 10117 Berlin, Germany; Bernstein Focus: Neurotechnology, Technische Universität Berlin, 10587 Berlin, Germany; Berlin Center for Advanced Neuroimaging, Charité-Universitätsmedizin Berlin, 10117 Berlin, Germany; Cluster of Excellence NeuroCure, Charité-Universitätsmedizin Berlin, 10117 Berlin, Germany; Department of Psychology, Humboldt Universität zu Berlin, 12489 Berlin, Germany; Clinic of Neurology, Charité-Universitätsmedizin Berlin, 10117 Berlin, Germany
| |
Collapse
|
6
|
Trevena JA, Miller J. Cortical movement preparation before and after a conscious decision to move. Conscious Cogn 2002; 11:162-90; discussion 314-25. [PMID: 12191935 DOI: 10.1006/ccog.2002.0548] [Citation(s) in RCA: 77] [Impact Index Per Article: 3.3] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [MESH Headings] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 11/22/2022]
Abstract
The idea that our conscious decisions determine our actions has been challenged by a report suggesting that the brain starts to prepare for a movement before the person concerned has consciously decided to move (Libet, Gleason, Wright, & Pearl, 1983). Libet et al. claimed that their results show that our actions are not consciously initiated. The current article describes two experiments in which we attempted to replicate Libet et al.'s comparison of participants' movement-related brain activity with the reported times of their decisions to move and also the reported times of their decisions of which hand to move. We also looked at the distribution of participants' reports over time to evaluate an alternative explanation of Libet et al.'s (1983) results. Although the Readiness Potential was usually present before all of the decisions to move, consistent with the findings of Keller and Heckhausen (1990) and Libet et al. (1983), we found that many reported decision times were before the onset of the Lateralized Readiness Potential, which measures hand-specific movement preparation. The latter finding is consistent with the conclusion that the LRP always started after the conscious decision to move. We conclude that even though activity related to movement anticipation may be present before a conscious decision to move, the cortical preparation necessary for the movement to happen immediately may not start until after the conscious decision to move.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Judy Arnel Trevena
- Department of Psychology, University of Otago, P.O. Box 56, Dunedin, New Zealand
| | | |
Collapse
|
7
|
Hammond G, Thompson T, Campbell L. Judgments of moving and intending to move in a timed-response task. PSYCHOLOGICAL RESEARCH 1993; 55:144-7. [PMID: 8356195 DOI: 10.1007/bf00419646] [Citation(s) in RCA: 1] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.0] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [MESH Headings] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 01/30/2023]
Abstract
Subjects performed a timed-response task in which they attempted to synchronize a rapid flexion of the index finger of their preferred hand with the last of a train of four regularly spaced acoustic clicks. The task was used to stabilize the execution time of a simple voluntary response in order to facilitate psychophysical judgments about the subjects' perception of having responded and of having intended to respond. In the first experiment, male subjects (N = 6) adjusted the appearance time of a reference stimulus (a brief percutaneous pulse to the responding finger) until it appeared to be simultaneous with their perception of having made the response. All subjects adjusted the reference stimulus to appear after response onset during the latter half of the force impulse. This finding suggests that the perception of having responded is based on peripheral feedback from the response. In the second experiment, male subjects (N = 6) performed the same motor task, but adjusted the time of the reference stimulus so that it appeared to be simultaneous with their intention to respond. Two subjects were not able to do the task successfully; the remaining four subjects adjusted the reference stimulus to appear from 101 to 145 ms before response onset. This finding suggests that the intention to respond is perceptually separable from the response itself and occurs at a measurable time before response onset.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- G Hammond
- Department of Psychology, University of Western Australia, Nedlands
| | | | | |
Collapse
|